Substitutions
==
v if
otherwise
slide: Substitution
A substitution
states that modifying by
assigning the value v to the variable x
then, for a variable y, the state will
deliver v whenever y is identical to x and
otherwise.
When we have, for example, an assignment
then we have as the corresponding transition
where ,
that is is like except
for the variable i for which the value 5
will now be delivered.
Whenever we have a sequence of actions
then, starting from a state we have corresponding
state transformations resulting in states
as intermediary states and
as the final state.
Often the states and are referred to
as respectively the input and output state
and the program that results in the actions
as the state transformer modifying into .
Program state -- $%f$
State transformations -- operations $a_1,a_2,...,a_n$
-
Correctness formulae -- Hoare logic
Verification
-
slide: The verification of state transformations
To characterize the actions that result from
executing a program, we need an operational semantics
that relates the programming constructs to
the dynamic behavior of a program.
We will study such a semantics in section \ref{10:behavior}.
The requirements a program (fragment)
has to meet may be expressed by using predicates
characterizing certain properties
of a program state.
Then, all we need to do is check whether the final state
of a computation satisfies these requirements.
Predicates characterizing the properties of a state
before and after executing a program (fragment)
may be conveniently stated by
correctness formulae of the form
where S denotes a program (fragment)
and P and Q respectively the pre-condition
and post-condition associated with S.
A formula of the form is true if, for every
initial state that satisfies P and for which
the computation characterized by S terminates,
the final state satisfies Q.
This interpretation of
characterizes partial correctness, partial since
the truth of the formula is dependent on the termination of
S (which may, for example, for a while statement,
not always be guaranteed).
When termination can be guaranteed, then we
may use the stronger notion of total correctness,
which makes the truth of
no longer dependent on the termination of S.
Pre- and post-conditions may also be used to check
invariance properties.
As an example, consider the following
correctness formula:
It states that the begin and end state of the
computation characterized by
is invariant with respect to the condition .
As an exercise, try to establish the correctness of
this formula!
To verify whether for a particular program fragment
S and (initial) state satisfying P
the correctness formula
holds,
we need to compute the (final) state
and check that Q is true for .
In general, for example in the case of non-deterministic
programs, there may be multiple (final) states
resulting from the execution of S.
For each of these states we have to establish that
it satisfies (the post-condition) Q.
We call the collection of possible
computation sequences of a program fragment S
the traces of S.
Traces characterize the (operational) behavior
of a program.
Assertion logic
Reasoning about program states based on the traces
of a program may be quite cumbersome.
Moreover, a disadvantage is that it relies
to a great extent on our operational intuition
of the effect of a program
on a state.
Instead, [Hoare69] has proposed using an axiomatic
characterization of the correctness properties of programming
constructs.
An axiomatic definition
allows us to prove the correctness of a program
with respect to the conditions stating its
requirements by applying the appropriate inference rules.
Axioms
- assignment --
- composition --
- conditional --
- iteration --
Consequence rules
-
-
Procedural abstraction
-
slide: The correctness calculus
In slide [10-correctness] correctness axioms have been given for
assignment, sequential composition, conditional statements
and iteration.
These axioms rely on the side-effect free nature
of expressions in the programming language.
Also, they assume convertibility between
programming language expressions and the expressions
used in the assertion language.
The assignment axiom states that for any post-condition Q we
can derive the (weakest) pre-condition by substituting the value e
assigned to the variable x for x in Q.
This axiom is related to the weakest pre-condition calculus
introduced by [Dijkstra76].
It is perhaps the most basic axiom in the correctness calculus
for imperative programs.
As an example, consider the assignment and
the requirement .
Applying the assignment axiom we have .
Consequently, when we are able to prove that P implies ,
we have, by virtue of the first consequence rule, proved that
.
The next rule, for sequential composition, allows
us to break a program (fragment) into parts.
For convenience, the correctness formulae for multiple
program fragments that are composed in sequential order are
often organized as a so-called proof outline of the form
.
When sufficiently detailed, proof outlines may be regarded
as a proof.
For example, the proof outline
constitutes a proof for the invariance property discussed earlier.
Clearly, the correctness formula for the two individual components
can be proved by applying the assignment axiom.
Using the sequential composition rule, these components
can now be easily glued together.
As a third rule, we have a rule for conditional statements of the form
.
As an example, consider the correctness formula
.
All we need to prove, by virtue of the inference rule
for conditional statements, is that
which (again) immediately follows from the assignment axiom.
As the last rule for proving correctness, we present here
the inference rule for iterative (while) statements.
The rule states that whenever we can prove that a certain
invariant I is maintained when executing the body of
the while statement (provided that the condition b is satisfied)
then, when terminating the loop,
we know that both I and hold.
As an example, the formula
while () i--;
trivially follows from the while rule by taking I to be true.
Actually, the while rule plays a crucial role in constructing
verifiable algorithms in a structured way.
The central idea, advocated among others by [Gries], is
to develop the algorithm around a well-chosen invariant.
Several heuristics may be applied to find the proper invariant
starting from the requirements expressed in the (output) predicate
stating the post-condition.
In addition to the assignment axiom and the basic inference rules
related to the major constructs of imperative programming languages,
we may use so-called structural rules to facilitate
the actual proof of a correctness formula.
The first structural (consequence) rule states that
we may replace a particular pre-condition for which we
can prove a correctness formula (pertaining to a program fragment S)
by any pre-condition of which the original pre-condition
is a consequence, in other words which is stronger than the original
pre-condition.
Similarly, we may replace a post-condition for which we
know a correctness formula to hold by any post-condition
that is weaker than the original post-condition.
As an example, suppose that we have proved the formula
then we may, by simultaneously applying the two consequence rules,
derive the formula
which amounts to strengthening the pre-condition
and weakening the post-condition.
The intuition justifying this derivation
is that we can safely promise less and require more,
as it were.
Finally, the rule most important to us in the present context
is the inference rule characterizing correctness
under procedural abstraction.
Assuming that we have a function m with formal parameter x
(for convenience we assume we have only one parameter, but this
can easily be generalized to multiple parameters), of which
the (function) body consists of .
Now, moreover, assume that we can prove for an arbitrary expression
e the correctness formula ,
with e substituted for the formal parameter x in both
the conditions and the function body, then we also have
that , provided
that P and Q do not contain references to local variables
of the function m.
In other words, we may abstract from a complex program fragment
by defining a function or procedure
and use the original (local) correctness proof
by properly substituting actual parameters for formal parameters.
The procedural abstraction rule, which allows us
to employ functions to perform correct operations,
may be regarded as the basic construct needed to verify
that an object embodies a (client/server) contract.
(C) Æliens
04/09/2009
You may not copy or print any of this material without explicit permission of the author or the publisher.
In case of other copyright issues, contact the author.